布兰代斯《论隐私权》
论隐私权的法律保护及完善
论隐私权的法律保护及完善作者:翟娅丽来源:《人民论坛》2012年第29期【摘要】隐私权是一项重要的人格权,对隐私权的研究在我国起步较晚,我国现有法律对保护自然人隐私权的规定存在很大缺陷,如内容零散,实体法与程序法之间缺乏统一性等。
对隐私权的法律保护,应根据我国国情同时借鉴国外先进立法经验,完善我国隐私权保护制度。
【关键词】隐私权名誉权立法完善1890年美国的两位法学家沃伦和布兰戴斯在《哈佛法律评论》发表了一篇名为《论隐私权》的文章,并在该文中明确提出了一种新的权利:隐私权。
该文的发表,标志着隐私权理论研究的开始。
而隐私权在我国的研究起步较晚,我国现有法律对保护自然人隐私权的规定存在很大缺陷,不能适应当前情况。
因此,加强对隐私权保护的研究和立法已经成为当前值得深入研究的一个重要话题。
隐私权的概念及特征关于隐私权的概念,由于中外学者对隐私的理解不同而有所不同。
美国学者William Prosser是通过归纳侵犯隐私权行为来对之加以定义的。
在国内,学界关于隐私权概念的观点颇多,通过对众多定义进行比较,张新宝在《隐私权的法律保护》中认为,“隐私权是指自然人享有的私人生活安宁与私人信息秘密依法受到保护,不被他人非法侵扰、知悉、搜集、利用和公开的一种人格权,而且权利主体对他人在何种程度上可以介入自己的私生活,对自己是否受他人公开隐私以及公开的范围和程度等具有决定权。
”①此定义揭示了隐私权的性质,包括了学界对隐私权所形成的共识—隐私权是一项独立的人格权②,属于人身权的一种,不具有直接的财产内容。
隐私权的内容丰富且广泛,包括私生活信息、私生活安宁及私生活事务等。
其法律特征主要有三个方面:一是隐私权主体具有限定性,隐私权的主体只能是依法享有民事权利资格的特定公民个人;二是隐私权客体的秘密性、真实性和复杂性,隐私权是以个人隐私为客体的权利,真实性和秘密性是其本质特征;③三是相对于普通民众而言,公众人物隐私权的保护范围基于国家公共利益以及公众知情权等需要而具有相对可克减性。
论隐私权及其法律保护
论隐私权及其法律保护1890年美国哈佛大血法学院的两位法学家路易斯·布兰蒂斯(Louis D. Brandeis)和萨莫尔·华伦(Samuel D. Warren)在当年的《哈佛法学评论》(Harvard Law Review)上发表了一篇著名的文章《隐私权》,这篇文章标志着隐私权的正式提出。
我国学者通常认为隐私权是指自然人享有的对其个人的,与公共利益群体利益无关的个人信息、私人活动和私有领域进行支配的具体人格权。
许多国家的宪法和法律都逐步确认隐私权作为一项受法律保护的独立的民事权利。
同时,隐私权作为一种国际人权,已经得到一些国际条约的确认和保护。
2001年2月26日,最高人民法院发布了《关于确定民事侵权精神损害赔偿责任若干问题的解释》,对隐私权作出了新的司法解释。
这是我国第一次以法律文件形式对隐私权予以正面保护。
但我国民法通则至今没能确认隐私权作为一项独立的民事权利进行保护,因此在审判实践中只能依据一些司法解释进行裁判,但一直不能摆脱将隐私权作为其他权利(名誉权或者人格利益)附属权利的阴影。
这都不利于对公民权利的保护。
本文通过对隐私权与知情权的概念介绍、对我国现有法律对隐私权的保护以及侵害隐私权的法律责任进行分析,进一步明确了隐私权的主体和客体以及保护方法,并对我国现有法律存在的不足提出了立法建议。
标签:隐私权;知情权;法律保护我国关于隐私权的法律不够发达,1986年制定《民法通则》时,没有直接规定隐私权的保护问题。
对此,学者一致主张应当对隐私权进行法律保护。
最高人民法院制定的《关于贯彻执行中华人民共和国若干问题的意见(试行)》采用变通的方法,对侵害他人隐私权,造成名誉权侵害的,认定应承担侵害名誉权的民事责任。
1993年公布的《关于审理名誉权案件若干问题的解答》,在第7条第3款明确规定:”对未经他人同意,擅自公布他人的隐私材料或以书面、口头形式宣扬他人隐私,致他人名誉受到损害的,应认定为侵害他人名誉权。
辩论是否应该注重隐私权辩论辩题
辩论是否应该注重隐私权辩论辩题正方,应该注重隐私权。
隐私权是每个人的基本权利,应该得到充分的保护。
首先,隐私权是人类社会发展的必要条件。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所言,“隐私权是人类文明的基石,是自由和个人尊严的保障。
”如果没有隐私权的保护,人们将失去自由和尊严,社会也将陷入混乱和不安。
其次,隐私权的保护对个人的心理健康和社会稳定至关重要。
心理学家阿伦·马斯洛曾指出,人的隐私需要得到尊重和保护,否则将导致心理问题和社会不和谐。
最后,隐私权的保护是现代社会法治精神的具体体现。
正如英国哲学家约翰·斯图尔特·密尔所说,“每个人都有权利决定自己的生活方式,只要不侵犯他人的权利。
”因此,应该注重隐私权,以保障个人自由和社会稳定。
反方,不应该过分注重隐私权。
隐私权的过分强调可能会对社会带来负面影响。
首先,隐私权的过分强调可能会对社会安全造成威胁。
例如,恐怖分子利用隐私权来隐藏自己的行踪和活动,从而给社会带来巨大的危害。
其次,隐私权的过分强调可能会妨碍社会的公共利益。
比如,在一些重大犯罪案件中,调查人员可能需要获取一些涉案人员的隐私信息来进行调查和取证,如果隐私权过分强调,可能会妨碍司法公正和社会正义。
最后,隐私权的过分强调可能会对个人自由造成限制。
正如美国总统富兰克林·罗斯福所说,“自由不是无限的,有时候需要做出一些牺牲。
”因此,不应该过分注重隐私权,应该在个人自由和社会公共利益之间寻求平衡。
结论,在隐私权的保护和社会公共利益之间寻求平衡是非常重要的。
应该根据具体情况,合理保护隐私权,同时确保社会安全和公共利益。
个人隐私权应该受到保护还是限制辩论辩题
个人隐私权应该受到保护还是限制辩论辩题正方辩手观点,个人隐私权应该受到保护。
个人隐私权是每个人的基本权利,应该受到保护。
首先,个人隐私权的保护是现代社会法治的基础之一。
作为一个现代文明社会,我们应该尊重每个人的隐私权,这是每个人的基本权利,也是社会秩序的基石。
如果个人隐私权受到限制,那么社会将会变得更加监控和压抑,人们的自由和尊严将受到侵犯。
其次,个人隐私权的保护对个人的心理健康和社会稳定具有重要意义。
在现代社会,信息技术的发展使得个人隐私面临更大的挑战,如果不加以保护,个人的隐私可能会被滥用,造成严重的心理伤害。
同时,如果个人隐私权受到限制,人们的生活将会变得更加焦虑和不安,从而影响社会的稳定和和谐。
最后,名人名句和经典案例也证明了个人隐私权应该受到保护。
比如,美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯曾经说过,“个人隐私权是一项不可侵犯的权利。
”这句话表明了个人隐私权的重要性。
另外,斯诺登事件也是一个经典案例,斯诺登揭露了美国政府大规模监控公民的行为,引起了全球的关注和讨论,这也再次证明了个人隐私权的重要性。
综上所述,个人隐私权应该受到保护,这不仅是每个人的基本权利,也是现代社会法治和社会稳定的基础之一。
反方辩手观点,个人隐私权应该受到限制。
个人隐私权的保护应该有所限制。
首先,个人隐私权的滥用可能会对社会造成危害。
在现代社会,恐怖主义和犯罪活动日益猖獗,如果个人隐私权得不到限制,恐怖分子和犯罪分子可能会利用隐私权来进行犯罪活动,从而对社会造成严重的危害。
其次,个人隐私权的保护也可能对社会的发展和进步造成阻碍。
在信息时代,个人隐私权的保护可能会对科学研究和社会管理造成一定的困扰,限制了信息的流通和共享,从而影响社会的发展和进步。
最后,名人名句和经典案例也证明了个人隐私权应该受到限制。
比如,美国前总统富兰克林·罗斯福曾经说过,“人民的利益高于个人的利益。
”这句话表明了在某些情况下,个人隐私权可能需要受到限制。
论隐私权的内涵
论隐私权的内涵【摘要】隐私权是个人对其不愿为公众所知,与人格尊严有关,与公共利益无关的信息利益的自由支配权。
隐私权的内容集中表现为两个方面:保护自己的隐私,禁止他人任何形式的窃取、披露和利用以及披露、利用自己隐私的权利。
隐私权是自由支配权,具有人格利益和财产利益双重属性,应纳入名誉权范围保护。
【关键词】隐私权;自由支配权;人格利益;财产利益自美国学者沃伦和布兰代斯于1890年在《论隐私权》一文中将隐私界定为一种“免受外界干扰的、独处的”权利后,隐私权日益引起学界、司法实务界的广泛关注。
经过多年发展,人们虽然对隐私权的内涵达成了一些基本共识,但在一些领域仍存在争议。
作为一种抽象、概括的权利,隐私权的内涵发展形成了多元纷争的现象,其基本问题有进一步予以澄清的必要。
一、隐私权的定义托马斯·库利是第一个将隐私权定义为“不受干扰的权利”的人。
①此说在隐私权最初研究过程中成为最常用的定义。
这种观点认为,隐私权是使得个人保持独处不受干扰的权利。
此说具有重要的历史地位,且为纷争多年的隐私权定义问题提供了统一的概念界定。
然而随着隐私权研究的逐渐深入,此观点的弊端也逐渐显露。
以“独处而不受干扰的权利”作为隐私权的定义,在概念上与“消极自由”并无差异。
②消极自由是指,在一定限度内,某一主体,可以或应当被允许,做他所能做的事情,或成为他所能成为的角色,而不受到别人的干涉。
③消极自由事实上区分了私人生活和公共生活两种领域,而为个体保留一个不容国家、政府或其他权威、抽象理念任加干涉的广大私生活范围。
以上隐私权的概念与此并无差别,由此造成隐私权的实质内涵与其他自由权并无明显区分。
此为该学说作为隐私权定义的最大缺憾。
信息控制理论认为,隐私权是个人、团体或公共机构自主决定何时、何种方式、在什么程度上与他人沟通自己的信息。
④该观点注意到了隐私权中主体对个人信息的控制权,较前一种观点有进步意义,然而依然存在不足之处。
首先,将隐私权定义为对个人信息的控制权,便有必要将“个人信息”的范围予以说明,但此观点在该方面定义模糊。
个人隐私权应该受到保护辩论辩题
个人隐私权应该受到保护辩论辩题正方观点:个人隐私权应该受到保护,这是一项基本的人权。
每个人都有权利保护自己的个人信息和私生活,而不受到他人的干扰和侵犯。
个人隐私权的保护不仅是对个人尊严和自由的尊重,也是社会秩序和法治的基础。
首先,个人隐私权的保护是现代社会法治的基石。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所言,“个人隐私权是美国宪法的核心价值之一,是人类文明进步的标志。
”保护个人隐私权可以防止政府和其他组织滥用权力,保护公民的自由和权利。
其次,个人隐私权的保护对于个人的心理健康和社会和谐也是至关重要的。
如果个人的隐私权受到侵犯,他们可能会感到不安和恐惧,甚至导致心理健康问题。
而且,如果个人的隐私被公开或滥用,可能会导致社会矛盾和冲突。
例如,曾经有一位名人因为个人隐私被曝光而导致家庭破裂,给自己和家人带来了极大的伤害。
最后,个人隐私权的保护也是对个人尊严和自由的尊重。
正如英国哲学家约翰·斯图尔特·密尔所说,“每个人都有权利按照自己的意愿生活,只要不伤害他人。
”保护个人隐私权可以让个人在不受外界干扰的情况下自由发展,实现自己的人生目标。
综上所述,个人隐私权应该受到保护,这不仅是对个人权利的尊重,也是社会秩序和法治的基础。
因此,我们应该加强对个人隐私权的保护,制定相关法律和政策,确保每个人都能够享有自己的隐私权。
反方观点:个人隐私权的保护应该适度,不能过度强调。
在信息化时代,个人隐私权和公共利益之间存在着一定的平衡关系,有时需要牺牲一部分个人隐私来保障社会的公共利益。
首先,个人隐私权的过度保护可能会对社会公共利益造成影响。
例如,在打击犯罪和恐怖主义活动时,有时需要对嫌疑人的个人信息进行调查和监控。
如果过度强调个人隐私权的保护,可能会给犯罪分子提供藏身之地,从而影响社会的安全和稳定。
其次,个人隐私权的过度保护也可能会阻碍科学研究和商业发展。
在医学研究和商业活动中,有时需要使用个人信息来进行统计分析和市场调查。
(完整版)论公众人物的隐私权的保护与限制法学毕业论文设计
一、隐私、隐私权与公众人物Ⅷ-第1页 共17页论公众人物的隐私权的保护与限制进入二十一世纪以来 随着科学技术的高速发展 经济水平的不断提高 人们在物质享受得到满足的同时 也逐渐把关注的目光转移到精神世界的欢愉。
正如古人云:“仓康实而知礼节,衣食足而知荣辱”。
人们开始更加注意对个体人格尊严的保护。
隐私及隐私权保护的问题成为社会关切及讨论的热点问题。
自然人 特别是一些公众人物 出于各种各样的原因和目的 热衷于带有以名誉权、肖像权、姓名权为表象的实质为隐私权的诉讼。
科学技术是一把威力无比的双刃剑 它的飞速发展在给人类生活带来极大便利的同时 也使人们的隐私一再外泄 私人空间越来越小 生活的安宁受到威胁。
作为受关注的公众人物的隐私权更是在强大的现代传媒技术面前无所遁形 成为个人私生活最容易遭到攻击的对象。
诚然 公众人物 特别是自愿性公众人物必须向社会让渡于本属于个人隐私的部分人格权 以此作为成名的代价 可是对于公众人物隐私权的限制 不能成为肆意践踏公众人物隐私权的借口[1]。
一、隐私、隐私权与公众人物要对公众人物隐私权进行深入分析 必先明确界定公众人物隐私权的内涵与外延 而公众人物隐私权的概念界定又是建立在对隐私、隐私权这两个基本概念的理解和把握的基础上。
因此 我们首先需要明确这几个基本概念。
根据史料的记载和研究 对于我们这个有着漫长的封建传统的国度 长期以来缺乏保护个人隐私的传统。
在十年浩劫的“文化大革命”中 个人人格权被践踏是中华五千年来的顶峰 国家主席都可以被任意抄家进行批斗 人格权的保证 人的尊严的保证 人的隐私权的维护 根本无从谈起。
目前 我国对人格权 特别是隐私权的维护 己经有了很大提高 但离人类理想的目标依然相差甚远。
在资本主义社会 新兴的资产阶级打出“人权”和“平等”的旗号来向封建阶级宣战。
但是在资本主义社会建立早期对人权的尊重并没有和个人隐私权联系起来 到1890年 两位注定要在历史上名流千古的美国学者沃伦和布兰代斯两人共同撰写的《论隐私权》一文发表在当年《哈佛法律评论》第4期上 从而确立了隐私权在法律意义的地位[2]。
论个人信息权与隐私权的边界
论个人信息权与隐私权的边界作者:王颖来源:《智富时代》2019年第12期【摘要】个人信息权与隐私权从实质上说是两不完全相同权利,隐私和个人信息有其相似之处,但两者并不等同,尤其是在大数据时代,两者关系更加复杂。
因此,应当对隐私权与个人信息权进行区分规定,才能适应现代化法治要求。
【关键词】隐私权;个人信息权;界分;法治一、从隐私到个人信息1、隐私权的产生与发展从历史的角度来看隐私的概念并不是自古有之,与之相同的隐私权的出现也比较晚。
直至1890年,沃伦和布兰代斯在《哈佛法律评论》上发表《论隐私权》(The Right to Privacy)一文,隐私权这一概念才真正被确立起来。
1948 年联合国大会通过《世界人权宣言》,其中第 12 条明确规定:“任何人的私生活、家庭住宅和通信不得任意干涉,他的名誉和荣誉不得加以攻击。
任何人有权对该种干涉或攻击享有法律保护。
”这成为隐私权最重要的国际人权法渊源。
在许多国家隐私权已经被确认为一项宪法性或民法性权利。
2、隐私权在我国的发展在中国,对隐私权的真正保护始于二十世纪八十年代初。
在近二十年的发展进程中,也就是在最高人民法院的司法解释出台之前,其保护呈现出一个总体特点法律零散、途径间接、手段脆弱。
最新的司法解释实现了对隐私权保护的巨大突破,体现了直接保护的方式,也体现了以人为本的现代法治理念。
我国司法实踐中最初将隐私置于名誉权之下进行保护。
2009 年通过的《侵权责任法中》第 2 条才直接承认了隐私权的地位。
我国宪法中没有直接提及隐私权,但是第 38 条“中华人民共和国公民的人格尊严不受侵犯”被认为是隐私权保护的宪法依据,体现出隐私权对人格尊严的维护。
2017 年 10 月 1 日开始正式施行的《中华人民共和国民法总则》在第 111 条对个人信息进行了规定,虽然并没有将个人信息权列为独立的民事权利,但是也为个人信息的保护提供了法律制度基础。
二、个人信息权与隐私权的联系隐私权与个人信息权之间存在一定的模糊区域。
浅析隐私权的民法保护及完善
浅析隐私权的民法保护及完善摘要:隐私权作为现代社会一项新兴的人格权,在受到人们越来越多的关注的同时,也遭受着越来越多的侵害。
为了使人们更好的理解隐私权,更好的保护自己的合法权益,本文在对隐私权的相关问题进行辨析的基础上,对我国隐私权的民法保护现状进行论述并提出相应的完善建议。
关键词:隐私隐私权民法保护1隐私权的概述自1890年,美国学者沃伦和布兰代斯在哈佛大学的《法学评论》上发表的《论隐私权》一文中第一次提出隐私权,至今一百多年的时间里,关于隐私权的概念界定出现了多种观点。
我们来看一下,我国学者的主要观点:佟柔先生认为,隐私权是公民对自己的个人生活秘密和个人生活自由为内容,禁止他人干涉的一种人格权。
①张新宝先生认为,隐私权是公民依法享有的居住不受他人侵扰以及保有内心世界、财产状况、社会关系、性生活、过去和现在其他纯属个人的不愿为外界知悉的事务的秘密权利。
②王利明先生认为,隐私权是公民享有生活安宁与私人信息依法受到保护,不被他人非法侵扰、知悉、搜集、利用和公开等的一种人格权。
③以上几种隐私权的定义,均从不同的研究角度,对隐私权的内涵做了揭示,笔者认为,王利明先生的定义最为精辟、准确。
2隐私权的民法保护我国民法对隐私权的保护,是一个逐渐发展变化的过程。
我国学者把它分为法律空白期、间接保护期、直接保护期、确认保护期四个阶段。
④本文将在下面对这四个阶段内涉及到的相关的法律条文进行论述。
2.1《民法通则》及相关司法解释对隐私权的规定在《中华人民共和国民法通则》中”人身权”脱离了对民事主体的依附,单独作为第五章”民事权利”的一节。
第一次在”人身权”中明确规定了姓名权、肖像权、荣誉权,但没有涉及隐私权。
这一阶段为法律空白期。
《关于贯彻执行〈民法通则>若干问题的意见(试行)》,第140条规定,以书面、口头形式宣扬他人的隐私,或者捏造事实公然丑化他人人格,以及用侮辱、诽谤等方式损害他人名誉,造成一定影响的,应当认定为侵害公民名誉权的行为。
辩论是否应该注重隐私权辩论辩题
辩论是否应该注重隐私权辩论辩题正方辩手观点:隐私权是每个人的基本权利,应该得到充分的重视和保护。
首先,隐私权是人类尊严和自由的体现,它保障了个体的自主权和自由选择权。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所言,“隐私是人类自由的基石。
”如果我们不尊重他人的隐私权,就等于侵犯了他们的人权。
其次,隐私权的保护对于社会的稳定和和谐至关重要。
如果每个人的隐私都可以被随意侵犯,社会就会充斥着不信任和恐惧,人们的交往和沟通也会受到严重影响。
再者,隐私权的保护也是信息安全和个人安全的重要保障。
在数字化时代,个人信息的泄露可能导致严重的经济损失和个人安全问题。
因此,我们必须注重隐私权的保护,才能确保社会的稳定和个人的安全。
反方辩手观点:隐私权固然重要,但在某些情况下,为了公共利益和社会安全,我们也需要对隐私权做出一定的限制和牺牲。
首先,隐私权并非绝对的权利,它需要在特定情况下与其他权利进行平衡。
比如,警方可以在调查犯罪时侵犯嫌疑人的隐私权,以确保社会的安全和公正。
其次,隐私权的滥用也可能对社会造成危害。
如果某些个人或组织利用隐私权来掩盖不法行为或进行犯罪活动,就会对社会造成严重危害。
最后,隐私权的保护也需要考虑到信息化社会的发展和需求。
在互联网时代,个人信息的交换和共享已经成为常态,为了促进经济发展和社会交流,我们也需要在一定程度上放宽对隐私权的限制。
综上所述,隐私权的保护是重要的,但在特定情况下也需要做出一定的牺牲。
我们应该在保护隐私权的同时,也要考虑到社会的整体利益和发展需求。
只有在平衡各种利益的基础上,才能更好地保护隐私权并促进社会的和谐发展。
个人隐私权应该受到更多保护还是公共安全辩论辩题
个人隐私权应该受到更多保护还是公共安全辩论辩题正方(个人隐私权应该受到更多保护):个人隐私权是每个人的基本权利,应当受到更多的保护。
首先,个人隐私权的保护是现代社会法治的基础之一。
隐私权的保护是个人尊严和自由的保障,是现代社会法治的基础之一。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所言,“隐私权是一种权利,而不是一种特权。
它属于每个人,不是政府的赏赐。
”因此,个人隐私权的保护是法治社会的基本要求,应当受到更多的保护。
其次,个人隐私权的保护对于社会稳定和和谐具有重要意义。
如果个人隐私权不受到足够的保护,那么社会将充满不信任和恐惧。
正如英国哲学家约翰·斯图尔特·密尔所言,“如果社会不尊重个人的隐私权,那么整个社会就会变得不自由。
”因此,个人隐私权的保护对于社会的稳定和和谐至关重要。
最后,个人隐私权的保护有利于促进创新和发展。
只有在个人隐私得到充分保护的情况下,人们才会愿意分享自己的想法和创意。
正如苹果公司CEO蒂姆·库克所言,“隐私权是创新的基石。
”因此,个人隐私权的保护不仅有利于个人自由,也有利于社会的创新和发展。
综上所述,个人隐私权应当受到更多的保护,这不仅是法治社会的基本要求,也是社会稳定和和谐的需要,更是创新和发展的基础。
反方(公共安全应该受到更多保护):公共安全是社会的重要基础,应当受到更多的保护。
首先,公共安全是国家的重要责任。
保护公共安全是国家的基本职责,没有安全就没有稳定,没有稳定就没有发展。
正如美国总统约翰·肯尼迪所言,“安全不是一种自然状态,而是一种不断努力的结果。
”因此,公共安全应当受到更多的保护。
其次,个人隐私权并不是绝对的,有时需要做出一定的牺牲。
在面对严重的安全威胁时,个人隐私权可能需要做出一定的牺牲。
正如英国首相温斯顿·丘吉尔所言,“没有人有权享受绝对的隐私权,特别是在面临国家安全的时候。
”因此,在一定的情况下,公共安全应当优先于个人隐私权。
个人隐私权保护辩论辩题
个人隐私权保护辩论辩题正方,个人隐私权保护是一项基本的人权,应该得到充分的尊重和保护。
首先,个人隐私权的保护是现代社会法治和文明的标志。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所言,“个人隐私权是一项基本的人权,是自由社会的基石。
”在信息化社会,个人隐私面临着更多的侵犯和泄露风险,因此更需要得到保护。
其次,个人隐私权的保护对于个人的自由和尊严至关重要。
如果个人的隐私不受保护,就会导致个人在社会中失去自由和尊严,甚至可能受到各种侵害。
比如,美国著名的水门事件就是一个典型的案例,政府对公民进行非法监听和监控,严重侵犯了公民的隐私权,引起了社会的广泛关注和谴责。
反方,个人隐私权保护应该在一定程度上让步于国家安全和社会公共利益。
首先,个人隐私权并不是绝对的权利,它需要在一定程度上与国家安全和社会公共利益相平衡。
正如英国前首相温斯顿·丘吉尔所说,“没有绝对的隐私权,只有绝对的国家安全。
”在反恐、打击犯罪等领域,国家需要获取一定的个人信息来保障社会的安全和稳定,这就需要在一定程度上限制个人隐私权。
其次,个人隐私权的保护也需要考虑到信息化社会的现实情况。
在互联网时代,个人信息的流动和共享已经成为一种普遍现象,个人隐私权的保护需要与信息共享和利用相协调。
因此,个人隐私权保护并不是一成不变的,需要根据社会现实和国家需要进行适当的调整和平衡。
在这个辩题中,我站在正方的角度,认为个人隐私权保护是一项基本的人权,应该得到充分的尊重和保护。
个人隐私权的保护是现代社会法治和文明的标志,对个人的自由和尊严至关重要。
同时,我也认识到个人隐私权的保护需要在一定程度上与国家安全和社会公共利益相平衡,但这并不意味着个人隐私权可以被任意侵犯和剥夺。
因此,我认为在保护个人隐私权的同时,也需要考虑到国家安全和社会公共利益的需要,寻求一个平衡的点。
论隐私权的内涵
论隐私权的内涵作者:赵笑然来源:《法制博览》2014年第06期【摘要】隐私权是个人对其不愿为公众所知,与人格尊严有关,与公共利益无关的信息利益的自由支配权。
隐私权的内容集中表现为两个方面:保护自己的隐私,禁止他人任何形式的窃取、披露和利用以及披露、利用自己隐私的权利。
隐私权是自由支配权,具有人格利益和财产利益双重属性,应纳入名誉权范围保护。
【关键词】隐私权;自由支配权;人格利益;财产利益自美国学者沃伦和布兰代斯于1890年在《论隐私权》一文中将隐私界定为一种“免受外界干扰的、独处的”权利后,隐私权日益引起学界、司法实务界的广泛关注。
经过多年发展,人们虽然对隐私权的内涵达成了一些基本共识,但在一些领域仍存在争议。
作为一种抽象、概括的权利,隐私权的内涵发展形成了多元纷争的现象,其基本问题有进一步予以澄清的必要。
一、隐私权的定义托马斯·库利是第一个将隐私权定义为“不受干扰的权利”的人。
①此说在隐私权最初研究过程中成为最常用的定义。
这种观点认为,隐私权是使得个人保持独处不受干扰的权利。
此说具有重要的历史地位,且为纷争多年的隐私权定义问题提供了统一的概念界定。
然而随着隐私权研究的逐渐深入,此观点的弊端也逐渐显露。
以“独处而不受干扰的权利”作为隐私权的定义,在概念上与“消极自由”并无差异。
②消极自由是指,在一定限度内,某一主体,可以或应当被允许,做他所能做的事情,或成为他所能成为的角色,而不受到别人的干涉。
③消极自由事实上区分了私人生活和公共生活两种领域,而为个体保留一个不容国家、政府或其他权威、抽象理念任加干涉的广大私生活范围。
以上隐私权的概念与此并无差别,由此造成隐私权的实质内涵与其他自由权并无明显区分。
此为该学说作为隐私权定义的最大缺憾。
信息控制理论认为,隐私权是个人、团体或公共机构自主决定何时、何种方式、在什么程度上与他人沟通自己的信息。
④该观点注意到了隐私权中主体对个人信息的控制权,较前一种观点有进步意义,然而依然存在不足之处。
布兰代斯《论隐私权》
4 Harv. L. Rev. 193Harvard Law ReviewDecember 15, 1890*193 THE RIGHT TO PRIV ACYSamuel D. WarrenLouis D. BrandeisBoston, December, 1890Copyright © 1890 Harvard Law Review Association; Samuel D. Warren, Louis D. Brandeis“It could be done only on principles of private justice, moral fitness, and public convenience, which, when applied to a new subject, make common law without a precedent; much more when received and approved by usage.”WILLES, J., in Millar v. Taylor, 4 Burr. 2303, 2312.THAT the individual shall have full protection in person and in property is a principle as old as the common law; but it has been found necessary from time to time to define anew the exact nature and extent of such protection. Political, social, and economic changes entail the recognition of new rights, and the common law, in its eternal youth, grows to meet the demands of society. Thus, in very early times, the law gave a remedy only for physical interference with life and property, for trespasses vi et armis. Then the “right to life” served only to protect the subject from battery in its various forms; liberty meant freedom from actual restraint; and the right to property secured to the individual his lands and his cattle. Later, there came a recognition of man's spiritual nature, of his feelings and his intellect. Gradually the scope of these legal rights broadened; and now the right to life has come to mean the right to enjoy life, — the right to be let alone; the right to liberty secures the exerc ise of extensive civil privileges; and the term “property” has grown to comprise every form of possession — intangible, as well as tangible.人身伤害――噪音与气味――精神价值的法律确认――名誉的法律确认Thus, with the recognition of the legal value of sensations, the protection against actual bodily injury was extended to prohibit mere attempts to do such injury; that is, the putting another in *194 fear of such injury. From the action of battery grew that of assault. [FN1] Much later there came a qualified protection of the individual against offensive noises and odors, against dust and smoke, and excessive vibration. The law of nuisance was developed. [FN2] So regard for human emotions soon extended the scope of personal immunity beyond the body of the individual. Hisreputation, the standing among his fellow-men, was considered, and the law of slander and libel arose. [FN3] Man's family relations became a part of the legal conception of his life, and the alienation of a wife's affections was held remediable. [FN4] Occasionally the law halted, — as in its refusal to recognize the intrusion by seduction upon the honor of the family. But even here the demands of society were met. A mean fiction, the action per quod servitium amisit, was resorted to, and by allowing damages for injury to the parents' feelings, an adequate remedy was ordinarily afforded. [FN5] Similar to the expansion of the right to life was the growth of the legal conception of property. From corporeal property arose the incorporeal rights issuing out of it; and then there opened the wide realm of intangible property, in the products and processes of the mind, [FN6] *195 as works of literature and art, [FN1] goodwill, [FN2] trade secrets, and trademarks. [FN3]This development of the law was inevitable. The intense intellectual and emotional life, and the heightening of sensations which came with the advance of civilization, made it clear to men that only a part of the pain, pleasure, and profit of life lay in physical things. Thoughts, emotions, and sensations demanded legal recognition, and the beautiful capacity for growth which characterizes the common law enabled the judges to afford the requisite protection, without the interposition of the legislature.法官对于新型权利的称呼是学术研究的关注点,再辅之以学术的论证,特别是社会情势的变迁。
个人隐私权是辩论辩题
个人隐私权是辩论辩题正方,个人隐私权是一项基本人权,应当得到充分尊重和保护。
个人隐私权的重要性不言而喻,它关乎个人的尊严、自由和安全。
首先,个人隐私权是人类文明发展的产物,它是现代社会法治和人权保障的基石。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所言,“隐私权是一项权利,它不应受到侵犯,而这个权利是人权的基石。
”个人隐私权的保护不仅是对个人尊严和自由的尊重,也是对社会公正和文明进步的保障。
其次,个人隐私权的保护对于社会的稳定和和谐也具有重要意义。
如果个人隐私权得不到充分保护,将会导致社会信任危机,加剧社会分裂和不安。
正如英国哲学家约翰·斯图亚特·密尔所说,“如果一个社会没有个人隐私权的保护,那么这个社会将会成为一个极权主义的社会。
”最后,个人隐私权的保护对于促进科技和经济的发展也至关重要。
只有在个人隐私权得到充分保护的情况下,人们才会愿意分享信息和参与社会活动,从而促进信息和经济的流通。
因此,我们应当坚决维护个人隐私权,使其得到充分的尊重和保护。
反方,个人隐私权虽然重要,但并不是绝对的。
在一些特定情况下,个人隐私权可能需要被适当侵犯。
首先,个人隐私权并非绝对的权利,它需要与其他权利和社会利益相衡量。
正如法国哲学家让-雅克·卢梭所说,“每个人都有权享有自己的隐私,但是这种权利并不是无限的。
”在一些特定情况下,例如国家安全、刑事侦查等情况下,个人隐私权可能需要被适当侵犯,以保障社会的整体利益。
其次,个人隐私权的保护需要考虑到科技和社会的发展。
随着科技的进步,个人信息的获取和传播变得更加容易,个人隐私权的保护也变得更加困难。
在这种情况下,个人隐私权的保护需要与科技和社会的发展相适应,不能一味地强调个人隐私权而忽视社会的整体利益。
最后,个人隐私权的保护需要考虑到个人的自由和责任。
个人隐私权不应成为个人逃避责任和违法行为的借口,而应当与个人的自由和责任相结合。
因此,我们应当在维护个人隐私权的同时,也要考虑到其他权利和社会利益的平衡。
个人隐私是辩论辩题
个人隐私是辩论辩题正方观点:个人隐私是辩论辩题对的,因为个人隐私是每个人的基本权利,应当受到尊重和保护。
在现代社会,随着科技的发展和信息的传播,个人隐私受到了越来越大的威胁,因此有必要对个人隐私进行辩论和保护。
首先,个人隐私是每个人的基本权利,这一点无可争议。
正如美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯所说,“个人隐私是一种权利,而非特权。
”这表明个人隐私不仅仅是一种特权,而是每个人的基本权利,应当受到法律和社会的保护。
其次,个人隐私的泄露可能导致严重的后果。
比如,2014年发生的“好莱坞裸照门”事件,许多好莱坞明星的私人照片被黑客盗取并公之于众,导致了严重的个人隐私泄露问题。
这种事件不仅侵犯了明星们的权利,也给他们的生活带来了极大的困扰和伤害。
因此,个人隐私的保护是至关重要的。
最后,个人隐私的保护也是社会稳定和发展的需要。
如果个人隐私得不到保护,人们的生活将会受到严重的干扰和威胁,社会秩序也将会受到严重的破坏。
因此,个人隐私的保护不仅仅是为了个人利益,也是为了整个社会的利益。
综上所述,个人隐私是辩论辩题对的,因为它是每个人的基本权利,其泄露可能导致严重的后果,而且也是社会稳定和发展的需要。
反方观点:个人隐私并不是辩论辩题对的,因为在一些情况下,个人隐私可能会对社会产生负面影响,甚至会危害公共利益。
因此,有时候需要对个人隐私进行适当的限制和监管。
首先,个人隐私并非绝对的权利。
正如美国总统理查德·尼克松所说,“在某些情况下,公众的利益可能会优先于个人的隐私权利。
”这表明在一些情况下,个人隐私可能会被公共利益所取代,因此有必要对个人隐私进行适当的限制。
其次,个人隐私的滥用可能会对社会产生负面影响。
比如,在一些犯罪活动中,犯罪分子可能会利用个人隐私来进行非法活动,这就需要对个人隐私进行监管和限制,以保护社会的安全和稳定。
最后,个人隐私的保护也需要考虑到公共利益。
如果个人隐私的保护过于偏执,可能会对社会的发展和进步产生负面影响。
辩论辩题是否应该受到法律保护
辩论辩题是否应该受到法律保护正方,应该受到法律保护。
首先,我们认为个人隐私应该受到法律保护,因为隐私是每个人的基本权利。
在现代社会,随着科技的发展,个人隐私面临着越来越大的挑战,比如网络监控、数据泄露等问题。
如果个人隐私不受到法律保护,那么个人信息很容易被滥用,给个人带来巨大的损失。
其次,个人隐私的保护也符合社会的整体利益。
如果个人隐私不受到法律保护,那么社会将变得更加不安全和不稳定。
比如,如果个人的银行账户信息泄露,那么将会给整个社会带来金融风险。
因此,保护个人隐私不仅是对个人权利的尊重,也是对整个社会的利益的维护。
最后,我们引用美国最高法院大法官路易斯·布兰代斯的名言,“隐私是一项权利,而不是一种特权。
”这句话充分说明了个人隐私应该受到法律保护的重要性。
反方,不应该受到法律保护。
首先,我们认为个人隐私并不是绝对的权利,而是需要在特定情况下进行权衡的。
比如,在刑事案件中,为了调查取证的需要,可能需要侵犯个人隐私。
如果个人隐私受到绝对的法律保护,那么将给刑事司法带来巨大的困难。
其次,个人隐私的保护也可能会对公共利益造成负面影响。
比如,如果某个人涉嫌危害社会安全,但是由于个人隐私受到法律保护,那么可能会给社会带来极大的危险。
因此,个人隐私的保护需要在公共利益和个人权利之间进行权衡。
最后,我们引用美国前总统理查德·尼克松的名言,“在公共利益和个人隐私之间,公共利益应当优先。
”这句话充分说明了在某些情况下,个人隐私可能需要被牺牲以维护公共利益。
综上所述,个人隐私是否应该受到法律保护是一个复杂的问题,需要在个人权利和公共利益之间进行权衡。
我们应该根据具体情况来决定是否给予个人隐私法律保护。
- 1、下载文档前请自行甄别文档内容的完整性,平台不提供额外的编辑、内容补充、找答案等附加服务。
- 2、"仅部分预览"的文档,不可在线预览部分如存在完整性等问题,可反馈申请退款(可完整预览的文档不适用该条件!)。
- 3、如文档侵犯您的权益,请联系客服反馈,我们会尽快为您处理(人工客服工作时间:9:00-18:30)。
4 Harv. L. Rev. 193Harvard Law ReviewDecember 15, 1890*193 THE RIGHT TO PRIVACYSamuel D. WarrenLouis D. BrandeisBoston, December, 1890Copyright © 1890 Harvard Law Review Association; Samuel D. Warren, Louis D. Brandeis“It could be done only on principles of private justice, moral fitness, and public convenience, which, when applied to a new subject, make common law without a precedent; much more when received and approved by usage.”WILLES, J., in Millar v. Taylor, 4 Burr. 2303, 2312.THAT the individual shall have full protection in person and in property is a principle as old as the common law; but it has been found necessary from time to time to define anew the exact nature and extent of such protection. Political, social, and economic changes entail the recognition of new rights, and the common law, in its eternal youth, grows to meet the demands of society. Thus, in very early times, the law gave a remedy only for physical interference with life and property, for trespasses vi et armis. Then the “right to life” served only to protect the subject from battery in its various forms; liberty meant freedom from actual restraint; and the right to property secured to the individual his lands and his cattle. Later, there came a recognition of man's spiritual nature, of his feelings and his intellect. Gradually the scope of these legal rights broadened; and now the right to life has come to mean the right to enjoy life, — the right to be let alone; the right to liberty secures the exercise of extensive civil privileges; and the term “property” has grown to comprise every form of possession —intangible, as well as tangible.人身伤害――噪音与气味――精神价值的法律确认――名誉的法律确认Thus, with the recognition of the legal value of sensations, the protection against actual bodily injury was extended to prohibit mere attempts to do such injury; that is, the putting another in *194 fear of such injury. From the action of battery grew that of assault. [FN1] Much later there came a qualified protection of the individualagainst offensive noises and odors, against dust and smoke, and excessive vibration. The law of nuisance was developed. [FN2] So regard for human emotions soon extended the scope of personal immunity beyond the body of the individual. His reputation, the standing among his fellow-men, was considered, and the law of slander and libel arose. [FN3] Man's family relations became a part of the legal conception of his life, and the alienation of a wife's affections was held remediable. [FN4] Occasionally the law halted, — as in its refusal to recognize the intrusion by seduction upon the honor of the family. But even here the demands of society were met. A mean fiction, the action per quod servitium amisit, was resorted to, and by allowing damages for injury to the parents' feelings, an adequate remedy was ordinarily afforded. [FN5] Similar to the expansion of the right to life was the growth of the legal conception of property. From corporeal property arose the incorporeal rights issuing out of it; and then there opened the wide realm of intangible property, in the products and processes of the mind, [FN6] *195 as works of literature and art, [FN1] goodwill, [FN2] trade secrets, and trademarks. [FN3]This development of the law was inevitable. The intense intellectual and emotional life, and the heightening of sensations which came with the advance of civilization, made it clear to men that only a part of the pain, pleasure, and profit of life lay in physical things. Thoughts, emotions, and sensations demanded legal recognition, and the beautiful capacity for growth which characterizes the common law enabled the judges to afford the requisite protection, without the interposition of the legislature.法官对于新型权利的称呼是学术研究的关注点,再辅之以学术的论证,特别是社会情势的变迁。
Recent inventions and business methods call attention to the next step which must be taken for the protection of the person, and for securing to the, individual what Judge Cooley calls the right “to be let alone.” [FN4] Instantaneous photographs and newspaper enterprise have invaded the sacred precincts of private and domestic life; and numerous mechanical devices threaten to make good the prediction that “what is whispered in the closet shall be proclaimed from the house-tops.” For years there has been a feeling that the law must afford some remedy for the unauthorized circulation of portraits of private persons; [FN5] and the evil of the invasion of privacy by the newspapers, long keenly felt, has been but recently discussed by an able writer. [FN6] The alleged facts of a somewhat notorious case brought before an inferior tribunal in New York a few months ago, [FN7] directly involved the consideration *196 of the right of circulating portraits; and the question whether our law will recognize and protect the right to privacy in this and in other respects must soon come before our courts for consideration.Of the desirability — indeed of the necessity — of some such protection, there can, it is believed, be no doubt. The press is overstepping in every direction the obvious bounds of propriety and of decency. Gossip is no longer the resource of the idle and of the vicious, but has become a trade, which is pursued with industry aswell as effrontery. To satisfy a prurient taste the details of sexual relations are spread broadcast in the columns of the daily papers. To occupy the indolent, column upon column is filled with idle gossip, which can only be procured by intrusion upon the domestic circle. The intensity and complexity of life, attendant upon advancing civilization, have rendered necessary some retreat from the world, and man, under the refining influence of culture, has become more sensitive to publicity, so that solitude and privacy have become more essential to the individual; but modern enterprise and invention have, through invasions upon his privacy, subjected him to mental pain and distress, far greater than could be inflicted by mere bodily injury. Nor is the harm wrought by such invasions confined to the suffering of those who may be made(隐私报道)的供给创造了需求the subjects of journalistic or other enterprise. In this, as in other branches of commerce, the supply creates the demand. Each crop of unseemly gossip, thus harvested, becomes the seed of more, and, in direct proportion to its circulation, results in a lowering of social standards and of morality. Even gossip apparently harmless, when widely and persistently circulated, is potent for evil. It both belittles and perverts. It belittles by inverting the relative importance of things, thus dwarfing the thoughts and aspirations of a people. When personal gossip attains the dignity of print, and crowds the space available for matters of real interest to the community, what wonder that the ignorant and thoughtless mistake its relative importance. Easy of comprehension, appealing to that weak side of human nature which is never wholly cast down by the misfortunes and frailties of our neighbors, no one can be surprised that it usurps the place of interest in brains capable of other things. Triviality destroys at once robustness of thought and delicacy of feeling. No enthusiasm can flourish, no generous impulse can survive under its blighting influence.*197 It is our purpose to consider whether the existing law affords a principle which can properly be invoked to protect the privacy of the individual; and, if it does, what the nature and extent of such protection is.上述部分就是问题的提出:如何能够保护个人的隐私?如果可以,则其保护的性质与程度是什么?Owing to the nature of the instruments by which privacy is invaded, the injury inflicted bears a superficial resemblance to the wrongs dealt with by the law of slander and of libel, while a legal remedy for such injury seems to involve the treatment of mere wounded feelings, as a substantive cause of action. The principle on which the law of defamation rests, covers, however, a radically-different class of effects from those for which attention is now asked. It deals only with damage to reputation, with the injury done to the individual in his external relations to the community, by lowering him in the estimation of his fellows. The matter published of him, however widely circulated, and however unsuited to publicity, must, in order to be actionable, have a direct tendency to injure him in his intercourse with others, and even if in writing or in print, must subject him to the hatred, ridicule, or contempt of his fellow-men, — the effect of the publication upon his estimate ofhimself and upon his own feelings not forming an essential element in the cause of action. In short, the wrongs and correlative rights recognized by the law of slander and libel are in their nature material rather than spiritual. That branch of the law simply extends the protection surrounding physical property to certain of the conditions necessary or helpful to worldly prosperity. On the other hand, our law recognizes no principle upon which compensation can be granted for mere injury to the feelings. However painful the mental effects upon another of an act, though purely wanton or even malicious, yet if the act itself is otherwise lawful, the suffering inflicted is damnum absque injuria. Injury of feelings may indeed be taken account of in ascertaining the amount of damages when attending what is recognized as a legal injury; [FN1] *198 but our system, unlike the Roman law, does not afford a remedy even for mental suffering which results from mere contumely and insult, from an intentional and unwarranted violation of the “honor” of another. [FN1]与诽谤、名誉侵权的区别;法律对于精神损害不提供任何救济It is not however necessary, in order to sustain the view that the common law recognizes and upholds a principle applicable to cases of invasion of privacy, to invoke the analogy, which is but superficial, to injuries sustained, either by an attack upon reputation or by what the civilians called a violation of honor; for the legal doctrines relating to infractions of what is ordinarily termed the common-law right to intellectual and artistic property are, it is believed, but instances and applications of a general right to privacy, which properly understood afford a remedy for the evils under consideration.The common law secures to each individual the right of determining, ordinarily, to what extent his thoughts, sentiments, and emotions shall be communicated to others. [FN2] Under our system of government, he can never be compelled to express them (except when upon the witness-stand); and even if he has chosen to give them expression, he generally retains the power to fix the limits of the publicity which shall be given them. The existence of this right does not depend upon the particular *199 method of expression adopted. It is immaterial whether it be by word [FN1] or by signs, [FN2] in painting, [FN3] by sculpture, or in music. [FN4] Neither does the existence of the right depend upon the nature or value of the thought or emotion, nor upon the excellence of the means of expression. [FN5] The same protection is accorded to a casual letter or an entry in a diary and to the most valuable poem or essay, to a botch or daub and to a masterpiece. In every such case the individual is entitled to decide whether that which is his shall be given to the public. [FN6] No other has the right to publish his productions in any form, without his consent. This right is wholly independent of the material on which, or the means by which, the thought, sentiment, or emotion is expressed. It may exist independently of any corporeal being, as in words spoken, a song sung, a drama acted. Or if expressed on any material, as a poem in writing, the author may have parted with the paper, without forfeiting any proprietary right in the composition itself. The right is lost only when the author himself communicates his production to the public, —in other words, *200 publishes it. [FN1] It is entirely independent of the copyrightlaws, and their extension into the domain of art. The aim of those statutes is to secure to the author, composer, or artist the entire profits arising from publication; but the common-law protection enables him to control absolutely the act of publication, and in the exercise of his own discretion, to decide whether there shall be any publication at all. [FN2] The statutory right is of no value, unless there is a publication; the common-law right is lost as soon as there is a publication.这里似乎谈的是知识产权(如著作权中的发表权)What is the nature, the basis, of this right to prevent the publication of manuscripts or works of art? It is stated to be the enforcement of a right of property; [FN3] and no difficulty arises in accepting this view, so long as we have only to deal with the reproduction of literary and artistic compositions. They certainly possess many of the attributes of ordinary property: they are transferable; they have a value; and publication or reproduction is a use by which that value is realized. But where the value of the production is found not in the right to take the profits arising from publication, but in the peace of mind or the relief afforded by the ability to prevent any publication at all, it is difficult to regard the right as one of property, in the common acceptation *201 of that term. A man records in a letter to his son, or in his diary, that he did not dine with his wife on a certain day. No one into whose hands those papers fall could publish them to the world, even if possession of the documents had been obtained rightfully; and the prohibition would not be confined to the publication of a copy of the letter itself, or of the diary entry; the restraint extends also to a publication of the contents. What is the thing which is protected? Surely, not the intellectual act of recording the fact that the husband did not dine with his wife, but that fact itself. It is not the intellectual product, but the domestic occurrence. A man writes a dozen letters to different people. No person would be permitted to publish a list of the letters written. If the letters or the contents of the diary were protected as literary compositions, the scope of the protection afforded should be the same secured to a published writing under the copyright law. But the copyright law would not prevent an enumeration of the letters, or the publication of some of the facts contained therein. The copyright of a series of paintings or etchings would prevent a reproduction of the paintings as pictures; but it would not prevent a publication of a list or even a description of them. [FN1] Yet in the famous case of *202 Prince Albert v. Strange, the court held that the common-law rule prohibited not merely the reproduction of the etchings which the plaintiff and Queen Victoria had made for their own pleasure, but also “the publishing (at least by printing or writing), though not by copy or resemblance, a description of them, whether more or less limited or summary, whether in the form of a catalogue or otherwise.” [FN1] Likewise, an unpublished collection of news possessing no element of a literary nature is protected from piracy. [FN2]版权法不能保护隐私That this protection cannot rest upon the right to literary or artistic property in any exact sense, appears the more clearly *203 when the subject-matter for which protection is invoked is not even in the form of intellectual property, but has the attributes of ordinary tangible property. Suppose a man has a collection of gemsor curiosities which he keeps private: it would hardly be contended that any person could publish a catalogue of them, and yet the articles enumerated are certainly not intellectual property in the legal sense, any more than a collection of stoves or of chairs. [FN1]The belief that the idea of property in its narrow sense was the basis of the protection of unpublished manuscripts led an able court to refuse, in several cases, injunctions against the publication of private letters, on the ground that “letters not possessing the attributes of literary compositions are not property entitled to protection;” and that it was “evident the plaintiff could not have considered the letters as of any value whatever as literary productions, for a letter cannot be considered of value to the author which he never would consent to have published.” [FN2] But *204 these decisions have not been followed, [FN1] and it may now be considered settled that the protection afforded by the common law to the author of any writing is entirely independent of its pecuniary value, its intrinsic merits, or of any intention to publish the same, and, of course, also, wholly independent of the material, if any, upon which, or the mode in which, the thought or sentiment was expressed.Although the courts have asserted that they rested their decisions on the narrow grounds of protection to property, yet there are recognitions of a more liberal doctrine. Thus in the case of Prince Albert v. Strange, already referred to, the opinions both of the Vice-Chancellor and of the Lord Chancellor, on appeal, show a more or less clearly defined perception of a principle broader than those which were mainly discussed, and on which they both placed their chief reliance. Vice-Chancellor Knight Bruce referred to publishing of a man that he had “written to particular persons or on particular subjects” as an instance of possibly injurious disclosures as to private matters, that the courts would in a proper case prevent; yet it is difficult to perceive how, in such a case, any right of property, in the narrow sense, would be drawn in question, or why, if such a publication would be restrained when it threatened to expose the victim not merely to sarcasm, but to ruin, it should not equally be enjoined, if it threatened to embitter his life. To deprive a man of the potential profits to be realized by publishing a catalogue of his gems cannot per se be a wrong to him. The possibility of future profits is not a right of property which the law ordinarily recognizes; it must, therefore, be an infraction of other rights which constitutes the wrongful act, and that infraction is equally wrongful, whether its results are to forestall the profits that the individual himself might secure by giving the matter a publicity obnoxious to him, or to gain an advantage at the expense of his mental pain and suffering. If the fiction of property in a narrow sense must be preserved, it is still true that the end accomplished by the gossip-monger is attained by the use of that which *205 is another's, the facts relating to his private life, which he has seen fit to keep private. Lord Cottenham stated that a man “is entitled to be protected in the exclusive use and enjoyment of that which is exclusively his,” and cited withapproval the opinion of Lord Eldon, as reported in a manuscript note of the case of Wyatt v. Wilson, in 1820, respecting an engraving of George the Third during his illness, to the effect that “if one of the late king's physicians had kept a diary of what he heard and saw, the court would not, in the king's lifetime, have permitted him to print and publish it;” and Lord Cottenham declared, in respect to the acts of the defendants in the case before him, that “privacy is the right invaded.” But if privacy is once recognized as a right entitled to legal protection, the interposition of the courts cannot depend on the particular nature of the injuries resulting.把他人信件公布是对私事的公开,在此个案中英国法官虽然提及了隐私权,但事实上还是依赖于传统的法律制度(如发表、侵害)加以审理。